Computing Reviews
Today's Issue Hot Topics Search Browse Recommended My Account Log In
Review Help
Search
Krister Segerberg on logic of actions
Trypuz R., Springer Publishing Company, Incorporated, New York, NY, 2013. 300 pp. Type: Book (978-9-400770-45-4)
Date Reviewed: Jun 27 2014

The first volume in a series by Springer on logicians, this book is on the contributions of Krister Segerberg. Segerberg is an outstanding practitioner of logic in the treatment of philosophical problems, many of them dealing with events, processes, programs, and routines, in which he includes recipes, selecting the options on a washing machine, and turning on the computer.

After an introduction by the editor of the volume, there are six chapters in the area of logics of actions, including two in the area of deontic logic, which deals with permissions and obligations. There are then seven chapters in the area of doxastic logic and belief change. Alchourrón, Gärdenfors, and Makinson (known as AGM) came up with an axiomatic treatment in 1985. In 1991, two papers by Katsuno and Mendelson, and by Grahne, had a different approach that they called belief update, and which Segerberg christened KGM. Segerberg pioneered the idea of using a logic of actions (he called it dynamic doxastic logic) as a way of dealing with belief revision, tying it up with the field of logics of programs.

A graduate student in the area of logic or in artificial intelligence will find a wealth of material here. Unfortunately, the book does not have an index. The authors forcefully argue the merits and demerits of different approaches. Can you imagine revising your current beliefs with the new belief b, and finding that as soon as you revise, you do not believe b? A clue: the belief b can be about beliefs; such statements were studied by the philosopher G. E. Moore. In this book, you will encounter the multiply layered models that handle such beliefs under the delightful name of “onions.” What I find remarkable is how Segerberg’s approach of handling many different things under the rubric of action and program logics makes them mathematically simple to handle, so simple that difficulties like the Moore statements become easy to spot. Even the first chapter by Richmond Thomason takes a critical stance, pointing out that for the requirements of artificial intelligence, Segerberg’s notion of routine is too simple. It is not a surprise when Johan van Benthem says in his chapter that it is hard to roam for long in modal logic without finding traces of Segerberg.

At the end, there are autobiographical and philosophical chapters by Segerberg, who went all the way from Sweden to New Zealand and back during his career. I was surprised to read about the conditions under which he studied in school north of the Arctic Circle. He also writes about his attempts to deal with academic isolation in Sweden. I was pleased that he remembered a short visit meeting students from all over India at a logic summer school in Jaipur, India, arranged by Biswambhar Pahi.

Several moving sentences remain in my mind. One is Segerberg’s comment about when a publisher suggested converting his doctoral thesis into a book. Segerberg says, “I was not a student of Dana Scott for nothing. Scott’s papers were always extremely well written: brilliant of content and elegant of style.” He declined to put something done in a hurry into print. Later, when he thought he had a publishable version, publishers were no longer interested. There is also the story of the now-famous Segerberg induction axiom for dynamic (and temporal) logic, and his feelings on discovering that his completeness proof for the logic had a gap. As he says, the matter does not seem so important today, but it is the humiliating experience of a mistake being found and corrected by someone else (it took logicians of the caliber of Rohit Parikh and Dov Gabbay) that rankled him. At the end, Segerberg comments on the professional hazards of being a quasi-itinerant scholar: “We go someplace, and for a limited time we develop an intense relationship with colleagues who feel like friends for life; and then we may never see them again.”

More reviews about this item: Amazon

Reviewer:  K. Lodaya Review #: CR142450 (1409-0737)
Bookmark and Share
  Reviewer Selected
 
 
Nonmonotonic Reasoning And Belief Revision (I.2.3 ... )
 
 
Logics Of Programs (F.3.1 ... )
 
 
Mathematical Logic (F.4.1 )
 
Would you recommend this review?
yes
no
Other reviews under "Nonmonotonic Reasoning And Belief Revision": Date
On the justification of Dempster’s rule of combination
Voorbraak F. Artificial Intelligence 48(2): 171-197, 1991. Type: Article
Mar 1 1992
Nonmonotonic reasoning
Brewka G. (ed), Cambridge University Press, New York, NY, 1991. Type: Book (9780521383943)
Oct 1 1992
Nonmonotonic reasoning in the framework of situation calculus
Baker A. Artificial Intelligence 49(1-3): 5-23, 1991. Type: Article
Oct 1 1992
more...

E-Mail This Printer-Friendly
Send Your Comments
Contact Us
Reproduction in whole or in part without permission is prohibited.   Copyright 1999-2024 ThinkLoud®
Terms of Use
| Privacy Policy